Death Row Inmates Reject Biden Clemency
The power of clemency, as enshrined in the United States Constitution, stands as both a symbol of executive compassion and a lightning rod for judicial debate. Theoretically, it offers a means to temper the rigidities of the law, a safeguard against the miscarriages of justice that inevitably arise in an imperfect legal system. Yet, in practice, the exercise of clemency often treads a precarious line, challenging the rights and strategies of those it is meant to benefit. Nowhere is this paradox more evident than in the recent refusals of clemency by death row inmates Shannon Agofsky and Len Davis, decisions that thrust the delicate interplay between mercy and justice into the spotlight, writes Gajanan Khergamker
Agofsky and Davis, inmates at the U.S. Penitentiary in Terre Haute, Indiana, have taken the extraordinary step of filing emergency motions to block President Joe Biden’s commutation of their death sentences. Their refusal is not an impulsive act of defiance but a calculated maneuver to preserve their legal standing. Both men argue that clemency—while sparing them from execution—would irrevocably harm their ongoing appeals and undermine their claims of innocence. In a justice system where procedural nuance often dictates outcomes, their choice encapsulates the complexities that clemency introduces.
Agofsky, convicted of the gruesome 1989 murder of Oklahoma bank president Dan Short during a robbery and later sentenced to death for killing a fellow inmate, stands at a legal crossroads. His court filing argues that clemency would strip him of the heightened judicial scrutiny afforded to death penalty cases, leaving his appellate efforts vulnerable.
For Davis, a former New Orleans police officer condemned for orchestrating the murder of Kim Groves, clemency represents an even graver risk. He maintains that his death sentence ensures continued public and legal attention to the alleged systemic misconduct that pervaded his trial. Both men, by refusing clemency, seek to force the courts to confront the substantive issues in their cases rather than allowing an executive act to sideline them.
This calculated defiance brings to the fore the profound tension embedded in the clemency process. On one hand, clemency is lauded as a humanitarian safeguard, a mechanism to correct injustices or provide relief to those who may not have received a fair trial. On the other, it often operates as a double-edged sword. Accepting clemency is frequently interpreted as an admission of guilt or, at the very least, a waiver of certain procedural rights. For individuals on death row, whose appeals hinge on claims of innocence or procedural error, this implication can be devastating.
The refusal of clemency by Agofsky and Davis forces a re-examination of its role in the justice system. The landmark 1927 Supreme Court case Biddle v. Perovich affirmed the President’s authority to grant clemency without the convict’s consent, underscoring the executive branch’s latitude in wielding this power. Yet, as their cases illustrate, clemency can inadvertently erode the procedural protections it is meant to complement.
The appellate process in death penalty cases is marked by rigorous scrutiny, a standard that often diminishes when a death sentence is commuted to life imprisonment. For Agofsky and Davis, the stakes are clear: clemency might save their lives but at the cost of undermining their legal avenues to vindication.
The implications extend beyond individual cases, touching on the broader philosophical and legal debates surrounding clemency. By design, clemency is a discretionary power, an acknowledgment that justice is not always served by strict adherence to the law. Yet, its exercise often raises questions about equity and fairness. Why should an act of mercy come with strings attached? Why should it require individuals to forfeit their claims to innocence or forego the procedural safeguards to which they are entitled?
The answers are neither simple nor uniform. In Herrera v. Collins (1993), the Supreme Court described clemency as the “fail-safe” of the justice system, a mechanism to address cases where new evidence emerges too late for judicial remedies. But this fail-safe is effective only when it operates in tandem with, rather than at the expense of, legal rights. When clemency becomes a tool that undermines due process or coerces admissions of guilt, it risks losing its moral and legal legitimacy.
The cases of Agofsky and Davis illuminate the complex interplay between clemency and justice, challenging the narrative of clemency as an unalloyed good. Their refusal to accept commutation underscores a fundamental truth: that justice is as much about process as it is about outcomes. Clemency, for all its virtues, must be exercised with an acute awareness of its implications, ensuring that it enhances rather than diminishes the rights of those it seeks to protect.
In this context, the power of clemency should not merely be a tool of mercy but a catalyst for systemic introspection. It must compel the justice system to confront its own fallibilities and recalibrate its priorities. Only then can clemency fulfill its dual role as a safeguard against injustice and a testament to the humanity of the law. In refusing clemency, Agofsky and Davis have not merely defied an executive decision; they have provoked a deeper reckoning with the very principles that underlie the American justice system.
To receive regular updates and notifications, follow The Draft News: